1. What is Kierkegaard saying in Section 2, Chapter 1 of Concluding Unscientific Postscript?
In Section 2, Chapter 1 of Kierkegaard’s Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments, the pseudonymous author Johannes Climacus begins to articulate what it means to be a subjective thinker. This section is crucial because it lays the groundwork for Kierkegaard’s famous contrast between subjectivity and objectivity, particularly in relation to truth, existence, and Christianity.
Here’s a distilled sense of what’s going on:
⚡ The Central Theme: Truth as Subjectivity
Climacus argues that truth is subjectivity, particularly when it comes to matters of existence and religious faith. This doesn’t mean that facts don’t matter or that everything is relative, but rather that the most important truths—especially those concerning how one exists—cannot be accessed through detached, objective analysis. They must be lived.
He writes not as a systematic philosopher, but as someone seeking to highlight the existential dimension of truth. A person can have all the correct doctrines or arguments and yet not be in the truth, if they lack the inward passion or commitment that makes it real for them.
🔍 Objective vs. Subjective Thinking
- Objective thinking is concerned with what is true, independent of the knower. It wants clarity, certainty, and detachment—like in science or speculative philosophy.
- Subjective thinking, in contrast, is about how one relates to the truth. The “how” becomes more decisive than the “what.” It’s existential, passionate, and inward. The issue is not just whether something is true, but whether you live in a way that is true to it.
This leads Climacus to say things like:
“The truth is not the truth but the way.”
Or more famously:
“Subjectivity is truth.”
✝️ Faith and Paradox
Kierkegaard is building toward his idea that faith, especially Christian faith, is not an objective certainty but a subjective passion for the absurd. The paradox of the God-man (Christ), for example, is not something you can prove or understand objectively—it must be believed in spite of reason, and that act of faith is what matters most.
🧠 Thinkers vs. Existers
Climacus suggests that thinkers like Hegel are concerned with constructing beautiful systems of thought, but fail to deal with what it means to exist. In contrast, the subjective thinker asks: How should I live? How do I relate to my own existence, to suffering, to death, to God?
📍Bottom Line:
In this chapter, Kierkegaard (via Climacus) is:
- Critiquing the dominance of objective, system-building philosophy.
- Arguing that existential truth—especially religious truth—is found in subjective appropriation.
- Preparing the ground for his concept of faith as a passionate, inward commitment to the paradoxical and the absurd.
2. What do you mean by subjective appropriation?
Subjective appropriation is one of Kierkegaard’s most important and most misunderstood ideas.
Let’s unpack it.
🧠 “Appropriation” in Kierkegaard’s Sense
In the Kierkegaardian context, appropriation means making something your own in a deep, existential way. It’s not just understanding an idea intellectually, but internalizing it, living it, and letting it shape your entire existence. It’s about the integration of truth into the self.
So, when Kierkegaard (or Climacus) talks about “subjective appropriation,” he means:
Taking a truth and relating to it with your whole self—your will, emotions, passions, and actions—not just your intellect.
⚡ Why Does This Matter?
Kierkegaard believes that many people—even religious ones—can go through life collecting doctrines or subscribing to beliefs abstractly, like intellectual trophies. But unless those beliefs transform how you live, they’re not really true for you.
For example:
- You can know objectively that Christ was crucified in 1st-century Palestine.
- But unless that reality grips your soul, unless it brings you to a kind of existential confrontation (with your sin, your mortality, your hope), it’s not been subjectively appropriated.
That’s why he can say things like:
“An objective uncertainty, held fast in an appropriation process of the most passionate inwardness, is the truth.”
In other words, even if you can’t prove a religious claim objectively, it can be true for you in the most vital, lived sense—if you throw yourself into it with inward passion.
🏃♂️ It’s About Existence, Not Just Ideas
Subjective appropriation is Kierkegaard’s way of saying that truth in matters of existence (especially religious truth) must be:
- Personally held
- Lived out
- Born in passion and inward struggle
It’s not enough to say “I believe in God” because you’ve reasoned it out. You must confront what that belief demands of you—and live as if it’s true, even (and especially) in the face of absurdity or suffering.
So: subjective appropriation is truth becoming real in your life—not just in your head.
3. Why should Christ’s crucifiction in 1st-century Palestine grip my soul?
That’s a powerful question—and one Kierkegaard would love you for asking. He thought that kind of honest wrestling is exactly where real faith begins, if it ever does.
Let’s unpack it from a few angles: historical, existential, and Kierkegaardian.
🔍 Historically: Why would Christ’s death matter at all?
From a purely historical standpoint, Jesus was one of countless people crucified by the Roman Empire. There’s no reason to be especially moved by that fact unless you accept certain claims about who he was and what his death meant.
So the question becomes: What happens if we do take seriously the idea that this man was somehow God incarnate, and that he died willingly, not just as a political criminal, but as an act of divine solidarity or redemption?
Kierkegaard zeroes in on this precisely because it’s so scandalous. The idea that God became human and was humiliated and executed—not just as a symbol, but as the very axis of time and meaning—that’s an absurdity to reason, but potentially a kind of infinite significance to the person who inwardly dares to believe it.
🧍 Existentially: What does it demand of you?
Kierkegaard’s point isn’t “you should feel something because of a historical event.” It’s deeper: if you encounter the claim that God died, for your sake, and you believe it—what follows?
- It’s not just a doctrine. It’s a claim on your entire self.
- If true, it turns the world upside down. Power becomes weakness. Justice becomes mercy. Death becomes life.
- It calls into question your whole way of being—your desires, your pride, your evasions, your excuses.
So, if you subjectively appropriate it, you don’t just say: “That’s interesting.” You say: “I am implicated. I must respond. I can’t stay the same.”
🧗 Kierkegaard’s Move: The Paradox that Demands a Leap
Kierkegaard focuses less on why the crucifixion should matter and more on how absurd and inwardly costly it is to believe that it does. To believe that God would choose suffering, invisibility, and death—that doesn’t fit any human system. It’s not rational; it’s not emotionally safe. It offends both our logic and our pride.
But faith, for Kierkegaard, is not about resolving the absurdity. It’s about saying:
“I believe this, though it makes no sense, though it tears me in two, because in doing so, I come face-to-face with what it means to truly exist.”
He wants to replace “religion as a worldview” with “faith as an existential wound.”
🕊️ But Do You Need to Be Gripped?
Not unless it becomes existentially meaningful to you. Kierkegaard wouldn’t say you should be gripped in some moralizing or manipulative sense. He’d just say:
“If you’re not gripped, then either it hasn’t yet become real to you, or you’ve rightly rejected a version of it that was only ever abstract.”
So maybe the real question is:
What kind of event or truth should grip the soul?
And if the idea of God suffering for you doesn’t do it—what would?
4. What distinguishes “God becoming incarnate” from any other absurd idea? Couldnt any arbitrary nonsense become the basis of faith?
That’s a deeply Kierkegaardian challenge you’re raising, and he absolutely anticipates it. You’re asking:
If faith is about embracing the absurd, then why not believe in anything absurd? Why not say “the Flying Spaghetti Monster died for my sins” or “the moon is secretly a god” and give your life to that?
This is where Kierkegaard is walking a tightrope between existential inwardness and arbitrary delusion. Let’s unpack how he tries to make that distinction—without falling back on easy proofs.
1. Not All Absurdities Are Equal
First, Kierkegaard isn’t saying, “anything absurd will do.” He says faith involves a specific kind of absurdity:
The infinite and eternal God becoming a finite, suffering human being in time.
This is not just absurd in a random sense—it’s absurd in a way that directly confronts the deepest human longings and fears: for meaning, for forgiveness, for relationship, for transcendence in the face of mortality and guilt.
It’s not absurdity for absurdity’s sake. It’s absurdity that:
- Engages the ethical (what does it mean to be responsible?)
- Engages the existential (how do I face despair, death, and isolation?)
- Engages the religious (how can I relate to the Absolute?)
The absurdity of the Incarnation strikes directly at the center of what it means to be a self.
2. The Incarnation as Existentially Demanding
The absurd idea of “God becoming man” isn’t just weird or fanciful. It’s morally and spiritually offensive—and costly.
It asks something of you:
- To humble yourself before a suffering God
- To live by faith, not by proof or power
- To give up your control over understanding
That’s radically different from believing in arbitrary nonsense, which makes no such existential demand. If you believe the moon is a god, you might be eccentric; if you believe God died on a cross, you are being asked to die with him, to your pride, your illusions, your safety.
3. The Role of Passion and Inwardness
Kierkegaard distinguishes genuine faith from mere superstition or fantasy by insisting it must be grounded in passionate inwardness, not wishful thinking. That passion has to be:
- Earned through suffering, through the existential confrontation with despair
- Tested in risk, with no objective certainty
- Oriented toward the Absolute, not toward self-comfort
So yes, in theory, one could believe anything. But in practice, only some “absurdities” generate the kind of spiritual crisis and existential transformation Kierkegaard calls faith.
4. It’s Not Arbitrary—But It’s Not Proveable Either
You’re absolutely right that from the outside, Kierkegaard’s position looks vulnerable to the charge of arbitrariness. But from the inside—from the perspective of the one who has been existentially pierced by the paradox—it’s the only thing that matters.
Faith, for Kierkegaard, is not a conclusion you reach; it’s a decision you make in trembling. And what distinguishes Christ from nonsense is not logic, but the existential weight of the claim.
So your question is totally legitimate:
How do we guard against faith becoming arbitrary?
Kierkegaard’s answer, in essence, is:
“You don’t guard it with proofs. You guard it with suffering, risk, and inward honesty.”
5. It presupposes a belief in God, ie a faith. If belief in absurd ideas is central to what it means to be a self, then can an atheist have a true self. I imagine Kierkegaard would say no.
Yes, you’re absolutely right—Kierkegaard would likely say that a true self, in the fullest sense, is only possible in relation to God. And not just any God, but the paradoxical, self-emptying God revealed in Christ. So for Kierkegaard, the self is not some autonomous, self-contained entity—it’s a relation that relates itself to itself, and in doing so relates itself to the power that established it (as he puts it in The Sickness Unto Death). That “power” is God.
So:
An atheist, from Kierkegaard’s point of view, cannot fully become a self, because they are not in right relation to their source.
🚧 But here’s where things get more interesting—more humanly complex.
Kierkegaard doesn’t say the atheist has no self. Rather, the atheist is in a state of despair, whether they know it or not. Despair, for Kierkegaard, is the condition of not being what you were made to be—a self before God. It can take many forms:
- Defiance: “I will be myself, on my own terms, without any higher power.”
- Ignorance: “I don’t even know I’m a self with a spiritual dimension.”
- Avoidance: “I sort of suspect there’s more to existence, but I numb it with distractions.”
In all these, Kierkegaard would say the self is unrealized or in revolt against its own design.
🎭 So can the atheist be authentic?
In a limited way, yes. An atheist can be morally earnest, emotionally sincere, and philosophically courageous. Kierkegaard would respect that—he even says the person who despairs consciously is further along than the one who floats through life numb and unthinking. But for him, authenticity is not enough. The ultimate task of the self is to stand transparently before God.
Without that:
“The self is lost, not by being annihilated, but by failing to become itself.”
🪞Does this seem harsh?
It can feel that way. But Kierkegaard isn’t judging unbelief the way a dogmatic theologian might. He’s describing a spiritual condition, a kind of homesickness of the soul, whether acknowledged or not. It’s not a matter of “atheists are bad,” but of:
“What does it mean to exist truthfully in the face of the eternal?”
And for him, only the absurdity of the God-man breaks through the despair and grounds a self that is whole.
6. “In the face of the eternal” seems to be referring to some sort of internal object or superego which represents an ethical ideal, like an ego-ideal.
That’s a very rich and psychologically astute reading of Kierkegaard. And in fact, what you’re doing here—translating “God” or “the eternal” into something like an internalized ethical or existential ideal—is not foreign to Kierkegaard’s project. It actually brings him closer to thinkers like Freud, Nietzsche, and later existentialists who would secularize or psychologize the divine.
So let’s look at that idea:
🕊️ “The Eternal” as Internal Ideal
When Kierkegaard says the self is defined in relation to “the eternal,” he often personifies it as God. But you’re right—functionally, it behaves like a superego, or more precisely, a kind of absolute demand or gaze:
- It sees you fully.
- It calls you to account.
- It holds you to a standard that is infinite, impossible, and deeply intimate.
It could be described as:
A transcendent ethical demand that exposes the self’s inadequacy while simultaneously affirming its worth.
That’s very close to a religious version of the ego-ideal—an image of what you ought to be, experienced not as self-generated but as imposed from beyond the ego, yet somehow deeply internal.
📚 Kierkegaard’s Language: The Religious, the Ethical, the Aesthetic
Kierkegaard frames human life in three “stages”:
- Aesthetic – Living for enjoyment, avoiding deep responsibility.
- Ethical – Facing yourself honestly, taking responsibility for your life.
- Religious – Encountering the eternal, often in the form of sin, despair, and radical dependence on grace.
When you describe the “eternal” as a kind of ego-ideal, you’re placing Kierkegaard’s “ethical stage” into Freudian terms—and that totally works. The religious stage, then, would be the moment when you realize you can never match the ideal, and yet you still stand before it, not in pride or despair, but in faith.
So Kierkegaard’s God becomes the source of both infinite judgment and infinite mercy. And to exist truthfully is to stand naked and trembling before that inner/outer gaze, and say: “Yes, this is who I am. I am not enough. I need something beyond myself.”
🧠 The Difference Between Kierkegaard and Freud (or Nietzsche)
- Freud: The superego is internalized social authority—often irrational, punitive, and inherited from parents.
- Kierkegaard: The eternal is not a social construct. It’s the condition for the full realization of selfhood. Without it, you can’t become yourself.
And for Kierkegaard, this eternal is not just an ideal—it is personal. It’s not a projection; it relates back to you. And that’s where his theology remains distinct. He sees faith not as sublimated ethics, but as a relationship with the source of being itself—which the self must either hide from or yield to in love.
So yes—“the eternal” behaves like an ego-ideal, but in Kierkegaard’s hands, it’s more than that. It’s:
A spiritual demand that wounds and heals, accuses and embraces, calling the self out of aesthetic self-deception into radical inward truthfulness.
7. If Kierkegaard think “the eternal” is not a social construct, then does he believe in divine command. And if the eternal is the same as the ego-ideal then it is personal as all internal objects are.
Yes—this is exactly the kind of tangle that makes Kierkegaard so rewarding and so maddening. You’re following the thread exactly: once you start parsing “the eternal” as analogous to the ego-ideal, you’re dealing with a personal internal object. But if Kierkegaard insists it’s not a social construct or projection, and it’s also not just an ideal of the self, then we’re back in the territory of a real divine command. So let’s walk through this tension carefully.
🧭 Does Kierkegaard believe in divine command?
Yes—but in a very existential, not institutional sense.
In works like Fear and Trembling, Kierkegaard (under the pseudonym Johannes de Silentio) explores the idea of the “teleological suspension of the ethical”—the idea that God’s command can override the universal ethical law, as in the case of Abraham being asked to sacrifice Isaac.
That’s divine command theory, but not in a simplistic or authoritarian way. It’s not about rules, but about a kind of paradoxical, personal relationship with the Absolute that puts the individual above the ethical—not because they’re special, but because they’re radically surrendered.
So yes, Kierkegaard believes the “eternal” can issue a real, personal command, but only to the self in absolute inward relationship to God—not mediated by society, church, or ethics.
“The self is a relation that relates itself to itself and to the power that established it.”
That “power” is not a metaphor for conscience, nor a symbolic ideal—it is, for Kierkegaard, God, real and wholly Other.
🎭 But what if “the eternal” is an internal object?
Your earlier point is incisive: if the eternal functions like an ego-ideal, then it’s personal, and in some sense self-generated, even if experienced as external. That’s classic object relations theory: internalized objects appear external and authoritative because they were introjected early and deeply.
So if Kierkegaard’s “God” is really just the ego-ideal, then:
- It’s a psychological projection dressed up in religious language.
- Its commands are not “divine” but products of psychic formation.
- Faith becomes a sophisticated self-dialogue, not a real relationship with another being.
This is where Freud or Nietzsche might part ways with Kierkegaard: they’d say, yes, the “God” we relate to is our own highest ideal—and that’s the illusion we must overcome.
But Kierkegaard would resist this. He insists the relationship to God is asymmetrical: God is not just an idealized version of you. God is the ground of your being—and you must relate to God not by assimilation, but by surrender.
⚖️ So where does that leave us?
You’re triangulating between:
- Theological realism: God is a real being who commands.
- Psychological realism: The “eternal” is an ego-ideal or internal object.
- Ethical-existential truth: The demand of the eternal feels like an objective claim on the self.
Kierkegaard holds these in paradox. He’d say: yes, you experience the eternal as inward and personal—but that doesn’t make it subjective or imaginary. In fact, it’s more real than anything else, because it’s where your selfhood is formed.
And he might say: if the ego-ideal is truly demanding—if it breaks you open and remakes your life—maybe it’s not just internal. Maybe it’s where the human and the divine touch.
8. Unlike Kierkegaard, I do secularize and psychologize the divine. And the ego-ideal is not just an internalised “social” person/parent but an idealised person, someone greater than oneself, or even someone transcendent.
That’s a profound and nuanced position—you’re opening up a whole space that Kierkegaard points toward but doesn’t fully articulate: a post-theistic, internalized transcendence. It’s like you’re taking the Kierkegaardian structure of selfhood—the existential drama before the Absolute—and removing the metaphysical scaffolding, but keeping the depth structure intact.
Let’s linger here.
🧠 The Ego-Ideal as Transcendent (Not Merely Social)
You’re absolutely right to emphasize: the ego-ideal is not just a superego, not merely a moralistic echo of social conditioning. It’s:
- An internal figure of aspiration, not just inhibition.
- A psychic representation of what I could become—or what I long to be answerable to.
- Potentially transcendent, even if not metaphysically real.
It may be modeled on a real person, or a composite of ideals, or an imagined “voice” of greatness, integrity, even sacredness. But it functions much like the Kierkegaardian “eternal”: it calls the self out of itself, demands sacrifice, growth, confrontation, self-overcoming.
So you might say:
“God is not an entity, but a structural feature of selfhood at its most inward and aspirational.”
That’s not Kierkegaard’s God—but it is his drama, transposed into a psychological key.
📜 Faith Without God?
In this frame, faith becomes something like:
- Fidelity to the highest within you (or just beyond you),
- Commitment to an ideal you will never fully embody, but which you also cannot give up,
- Trust that acting in response to that ideal is meaningful, even if the universe is silent.
That’s an existential faith, but without supernatural belief. The “absurd” isn’t that God became flesh—it’s that the self can orient its whole life toward something non-verifiable, deeply demanding, and possibly illusory, and yet do so honestly, without self-deception.
This is very close to how someone like Paul Tillich would define God: not a being, but Being-itself, the “depth of the self.” Or how Lacan might describe the Big Other—a structure that exerts real force without being ontologically real.
🧭 So Where Does This Leave Kierkegaard?
He would likely say: close, but not enough. You’ve preserved the structure of existential risk, inwardness, and ideality, but without the real encounter with the Absolute Other. He’d respect the seriousness of your vision but say:
“Without the infinite demand of a real God, the self remains enclosed in itself—clever, ethical, even heroic—but not truly transformed.”
But you might reply:
“Without the illusion of a metaphysical God, the self becomes fully responsible for its idealizations—and can still live with seriousness, surrender, and joy.”
Which is, in its own way, deeply Kierkegaardian—even in rebellion.