Kant and Critique of Pure Reason

What is the central problem that Kant addresses in Critique of Pure Reason between the rationalists (Leibniz, Spinoza) and the empiricists (Hume)?

The central problem Kant addresses in the Critique of Pure Reason is how knowledge is possible—specifically, how synthetic a priori knowledge is possible—and this arises from the conflict between rationalism and empiricism.

Here’s how that plays out:

1. The Rationalist View (e.g., Leibniz, Spinoza):

  • Knowledge comes primarily from reason.
  • The mind has innate ideas or logical structures that allow it to access truths about the world independently of experience.
  • They claim that we can have certain knowledge of metaphysical truths (e.g., God, the soul, causality) through reason alone.

2. The Empiricist View (e.g., Locke, Berkeley, Hume):

  • All knowledge comes from experience.
  • The mind begins as a blank slate (tabula rasa).
  • Metaphysical concepts that go beyond experience—like God, substance, or causality—are not justified.
  • Hume, especially, argues that key concepts like causality are not rationally justifiable—they are just habits of thought based on repeated experience.

Kant’s Central Problem:

How are synthetic a priori judgments possible?

  • Synthetic: the predicate adds something not contained in the subject (e.g., “The shortest path between two points is a straight line”).
  • A priori: known independently of experience.

Kant believed both camps were partly right and partly wrong:

  • He agreed with Hume that we can’t derive concepts like causality from experience.
  • But he also thought rationalists went too far in claiming we can know metaphysical truths independent of all experience.

Kant’s Solution: The “Copernican Revolution”

Rather than assuming our knowledge must conform to objects, Kant reverses the approach:

“Objects must conform to our knowledge.”

  • Our mind actively structures experience using a priori concepts like space, time, and the categories of understanding (e.g., causality, substance).
  • So we can have synthetic a priori knowledge—but only about phenomena, not noumena (things-in-themselves).

In Summary:

Kant seeks a middle ground:

  • He wants to secure the certainty of science (against Humean skepticism).
  • But he also wants to set limits on metaphysical speculation (against rationalist overreach).
  • Thus, he redefines the conditions under which objective knowledge is possible—grounding it in the structure of human cognition itself.

Does transcendental realism have anything to do with things in themselves?

Yes, transcendental realism has everything to do with things in themselves—but in a way that Kant ultimately rejects.

Here’s the relationship:


🧠 What is Transcendental Realism?

Kant defines transcendental realism as the view that:

  • Things in themselves (the noumenal world) exist in the same way and with the same structure as the appearances (phenomena) we perceive.
  • In other words, reality is as it appears, and we can potentially come to know things as they are in themselves—a view shared (in different ways) by both rationalists and empiricists.

This is the default metaphysical assumption of much pre-Kantian philosophy.


🔁 But Kant says: Not so fast.

Kant rejects transcendental realism in favor of transcendental idealism:

We cannot know things as they are in themselves, but only as they appear to us, through the forms of space and time and the categories (like causality, substance, etc.).

  • Space and time are not features of the world in itself but forms of our intuition.
  • The categories (e.g., causality, unity, plurality) are not applied by reality to our mind but are applied by the mind to the data of experience.
  • Thus, the “thing in itself” (Ding an sich) is real, but unknowable.

🧩 So how does this connect?

Transcendental realism assumes we experience things as they are in themselves.

Kant’s critique shows that this leads to contradictions (e.g., in metaphysics: the antinomies, like whether the world has a beginning in time or not).

So he says:

  • To avoid these contradictions, we must stop projecting our conceptual structures onto the world as it is in itself.
  • Instead, we should see these structures as conditions of how we experience the world.

⚖️ In sum:

Transcendental RealismTranscendental Idealism (Kant)
World as it isKnowable (eventually)Exists, but unknowable
Space and TimeProperties of things in themselvesForms of human intuition
Categories (e.g., causality)Inherent in objectsImposed by the mind
ResultLeads to metaphysical illusionsGrounds empirical science, limits metaphysics

Why does transcendental idealism ground empirical science?

Transcendental idealism grounds empirical science by explaining how objective knowledge of experience is possible in the first place. Here’s how that works:


👓 1. The Basic Move: The Mind Structures Experience

Kant argues that in order for science (like Newtonian physics) to give us necessary and universal knowledge of the world, something more than raw sense-data is needed.

So he proposes this:

The mind doesn’t just receive information—it actively organizes it using built-in structures:

  • Space and time: the forms of intuition (how we perceive things).
  • Categories: like causality, substance, quantity—these are applied by the understanding to organize sensory data into coherent experience.

🧠 → So empirical reality (the world as we experience it) is already shaped by these mental forms.


🧪 2. Why This Grounds Science:

  • Science relies on universal and necessary laws (e.g., “Every event has a cause”).
  • But if we were just passively receiving sensations, like Hume thought, we could never justify such laws—they’d just be habits of thought.
  • Transcendental idealism, by contrast, says: Causality is not inferred from experience—it is a condition for having experience in the first place.

💡 We can have scientific laws about nature because nature itself is what appears to us through these lawful structures.


⚙️ 3. So Empirical Science Is:

  • Not about the noumenal world (things in themselves).
  • But about the phenomenal world—the structured, law-governed world that arises when sensibility (intuition) is shaped by understanding (categories).

This phenomenal world is:

  • Systematic (because the mind unifies experience).
  • Predictable (because the same structures apply to all experiences).
  • Knowable through reason and observation.

Hence: empirical science is possible and justified—because the world it studies is already structured by the mind in a lawful way.


🎯 TL;DR

Transcendental idealism says:

We can have objective scientific knowledge because the mind imposes the very conditions (space, time, causality, etc.) that make such knowledge possible.

It solves the problem Hume raised—how can we know laws like causality?—and explains why science works, without assuming we know the world “as it is in itself.”


But if science is based on the phenomenal world, surely that in turn must be based on the noumenal world, and that how we know about things in themselves?

If the phenomenal world (the world of experience) is a structured appearance, doesn’t it have to be an appearance of something—i.e., the noumenal world (things in themselves)?
And if so, aren’t we, in some indirect way, knowing the noumenal through its effects?

This is a huge philosophical pressure point. Let’s unpack what Kant says—and the problems it creates.


🔍 1. Kant’s Position: Two Realms

Kant distinguishes between:

  • Phenomena: things as they appear to us, structured by space, time, and the categories.
  • Noumena: things in themselves, which exist independently of our cognition but are unknowable.

So, you’re right to think:

The phenomenal world must be grounded in the noumenal, or else we’re stuck with appearances of… nothing?

Kant concedes this, kind of:

“There must be something that corresponds to our representations… but we can never know it as it is in itself.”

So: yes, things in themselves are the source of the sensory input that gets structured into experience—but we can’t say what they are like beyond that they must exist to explain the appearances.


🔁 2. But Can’t We Know Something About Them?

This is where your intuition is totally valid. Many readers and critics ask:

If the noumenal causes the phenomenal, then causality must somehow apply across that boundary, right?

But Kant explicitly says:

  • Causality is a category of the understanding.
  • It only applies within the phenomenal realm.
  • Applying it to the noumenal realm would be a category mistake.

This leads to a tension:

  • On one hand, Kant needs the noumenal to explain why we have any experience at all.
  • On the other hand, he says we can’t know or even say anything positive about it.

So we end up with a kind of epistemic firewall:

  • We can’t know the noumenal.
  • But we must assume it.

🧭 3. So Do We Know Things in Themselves?

Kant’s answer is subtle:

  • We do not know them.
  • But we are entitled to think them—as a regulative idea, not a constitutive one.

So:

  • We don’t gain knowledge of things in themselves.
  • But we acknowledge their existence as the boundary condition of experience.

🧨 4. Why This Is a Big Philosophical Problem

This leads to famous critiques:

  • Fichte, Schelling, Hegel: Thought Kant’s “thing in itself” was incoherent—you can’t have a causal relation to something you’re not allowed to describe causally.
  • Schopenhauer: Accepted Kant’s framework but said we can access the noumenal through will, not concepts.
  • Contemporary take: Kant draws a curtain between appearance and reality but won’t say what’s behind it—and yet insists there is something.

So your instinct is right:

If the phenomenal is grounded in the noumenal, how can Kant avoid saying we know something about it?

Answer: He tries to hold the line by saying we can think the noumenal but never know it. But many think this is a deep crack in his system.


✨ TL;DR:

  • Yes, the phenomenal world depends on the noumenal.
  • No, Kant says we can’t know anything about the noumenal (only that it must exist).
  • This creates a tension—he needs the noumenal to explain experience but forbids us from describing it.
  • Whether this holds up is one of the biggest debates Kant left behind.

So what was Hegels critique of Kant?

Hegel’s critique of Kant is profound and multi-layered. He admired Kant, saw him as a philosophical turning point—but also believed Kant didn’t go far enough. Here’s the heart of it:


🧱 Hegel’s Big Critique: The Thing-in-Itself and the Limits of Reason

1. Kant draws a line between what we can know (phenomena) and what we can’t (noumena).

  • Hegel says: ❌ That line is the problem.

He thought it was self-defeating for Kant to say:

“Human reason is limited, and here are the limits I’ve discovered using… reason.”

In Hegel’s eyes:

  • Kant’s system admits something real (the noumenal), depends on it to explain experience, but then says we can’t know or think it adequately.
  • That creates a kind of dualism or split:
    • Between subject and object,
    • Appearance and reality,
    • Understanding and reason.

👉 Hegel wants to overcome this dualism by showing that what we call “reality” and what we call “thought” are not two separate things but moments within a single dynamic process.


🌱 So what does Hegel do instead?

He says:

Let’s not stop at the categories; let’s let thought develop itself fully and show that reality is, in some sense, rational all the way down.

This leads to his concept of:

🔁 Absolute Idealism

  • The real is rational, and the rational is real.
  • There is no unknowable “thing in itself” standing apart from thought.
  • Instead, reality is self-developing Spirit (Geist)—a process that unfolds through contradiction, negation, and self-overcoming.
  • Human thought is not separate from the world—it’s the medium through which Spirit comes to know itself.

🧠 The Dialectic: Hegel’s Method

Kant’s categories are static: they organize experience.

Hegel says: But reality moves. So should thought.

  • Thesis → Antithesis → Synthesis
    • Every concept contains a contradiction that pushes it forward.
    • So knowledge evolves—not by hitting a wall (like Kant’s noumenal barrier), but by working through contradictions to reach higher, more adequate forms.

👉 So instead of limits (Kant), Hegel offers development—reason working through history, art, religion, politics, etc.


💥 Key Points of Critique

KantHegel
Noumenal vs Phenomenal (split reality)Reality is a unified rational process
Categories as fixed formsCategories evolve dialectically
Limits of reasonReason is infinite in scope—self-developing
Moral freedom as beyond knowledgeFreedom is realized in history and community
Thing-in-itself unknowableThere is no “thing” outside of thought—only developing Spirit

🏁 TL;DR

Hegel’s critique of Kant in a sentence:

“Kant showed the limits of reason, but then reified them. I will show how reason, through dialectic, overcomes its own limits and becomes fully at home in the world.”

He replaces Kant’s cautious dualism with a sweeping, dynamic philosophy of becoming—where truth is the whole, and that whole is Spirit coming to know itself.


What are “Categories” referring to?


🧠 What Are “Categories” in Kant?

In Critique of Pure Reason, Categories are pure concepts of the understanding—they are the basic mental structures that the mind uses to organize experience.

They are not learned from experience. They are a priori—built into the mind.
And they are necessary for any coherent experience to occur.


🔧 Metaphor: The Mind as a Projector

Imagine your mind is like a projector:

  • The senses provide the raw data (colors, sounds, shapes).
  • But that data would be meaningless chaos unless the projector structured it in a particular way.

The Categories are like the lenses in the projector:

  • They determine how the raw data is shaped into a coherent image of the world.
  • Without them, we wouldn’t experience objects or events—just disconnected sensations.

🧩 Examples of Categories

Kant organizes them into four main groups, each with three subcategories. Here’s a simplified version:

GroupCategories (some examples)What They Do
QuantityUnity, Plurality, TotalityAllow us to grasp things as “one,” “many,” or “whole.”
QualityReality, Negation, LimitationLet us perceive presence/absence, degrees of intensity.
RelationInherence (substance/accident), Causality, Community (reciprocal interaction)Let us understand how things relate (e.g., this causes that).
ModalityPossibility, Existence, NecessityLet us judge whether something could, does, or must exist.

🧱 Why Categories Matter

According to Kant:

  • We never experience “things in themselves.”
  • What we experience is the result of our mind shaping sensory data through:
    1. Forms of Intuition: Space and Time (they structure what appears).
    2. Categories of the Understanding: (they structure how it appears as something).

💡 So categories are the condition for the possibility of experience.


⚠️ Important Clarification

  • Categories are not just abstract concepts like “cause” or “substance” that we apply when we reflect.
  • They are pre-reflective, structuring operations—like grammar rules you use when speaking, even if you don’t know you’re using them.

🔁 Compare to Hume

  • Hume said we have no justification for causality—we just habitually expect causes.
  • Kant replies: No—causality is a necessary condition for experience itself. Without it, you wouldn’t perceive any sequence of events as meaningful.

🏁 TL;DR:

Categories are the mental scaffolding that shapes how we experience and understand the world.
They are not derived from experience, but rather, they make experience itself possible.


Like logical or mathematical operators?

Yes! Categories are a bit like logical or mathematical operators, but they operate at a deeper, pre-conscious level. Let’s run with that idea:


🧠 Categories as “Operators of Experience”

Just like:

  • In math, operators like +, , ×, = let you structure quantities into meaningful equations.
  • In logic, operators like AND, OR, NOT, IF...THEN let you structure propositions into valid arguments.

👉 Categories, for Kant, are the fundamental operators of thought that let you structure raw sensory data into meaningful, coherent objects and events.


🧩 Example: Causality as an Operator

Imagine you see:

Lightning ⚡ → Thunder 🔊

Without the category of causality, you’d just register a flash and a sound—no connection.

But because your mind automatically applies the category of causality, you experience:

“The lightning caused the thunder.”

It’s not that you observe causality like you observe light or sound—you impose it.
That’s why Kant calls the categories “pure concepts of the understanding”—they don’t come from experience; they structure it.


💡 Key Differences from Logic/Math Operators

FeatureLogic/Math OperatorsKant’s Categories
Learned or innate?LearnedInnate (a priori)
Domain of operationPropositions / numbersRaw experience / perception
Conscious application?Often consciousMostly pre-conscious
Can be changed/overridden?YesNo—they’re necessary for experience

📦 Another Metaphor: Categories as “Mental Templates”

Think of categories as templates or filters that your mind uses to construct a world that makes sense.

You don’t see “substance,” “plurality,” or “possibility” floating around—you see tables, dogs, storms, etc., and the categories are what make those things appear to you as coherent objects and events.


🏁 TL;DR

Yes—they function like logical/mathematical operators, but they are deeper, non-optional, and preconditions for experiencing a world at all.
They’re the mind’s built-in rules for making a world intelligible.


So what was Schopenhauser’s position on all this?

Schopenhauer—Kant’s moody, brilliant, and rather goth philosophical heir. 🖤☕️

Schopenhauer loved Kant. He once said:

“I could not have written my own philosophy without Kant’s having cleared the ground for me.”

But he also thought Kant left something crucial unfinished—and Schopenhauer was going to fix that.


🧠 Schopenhauer’s Core Move:

Kant was right: the world as we experience it is phenomenal, shaped by our mind (space, time, causality, categories).

But Kant was wrong to say the noumenal (thing-in-itself) is unknowable.

Instead, Schopenhauer says:

We do have access to the thing-in-itself—not through reason, not through science, but through our own inner experience.


🔁 1. Kant’s Two Worlds—Reframed

KantSchopenhauer
Phenomenon: appearanceRepresentation (“Vorstellung”)
Noumenon: thing-in-itselfWill (“Wille”)

He agrees:

  • The world we see and measure is shaped by our mind’s forms (space, time, causality).
  • This world is a representation, not the thing itself.

But then he asks:

Is there any part of reality we experience from the inside?

Yes: ourselves.


🧍 2. Self-Knowledge: The Window to the Noumenal

  • When you look at your own body from the outside, it’s a phenomenon like anything else.
  • But when you feel hunger, desire, pain, striving, you’re experiencing yourself from the inside—not as appearance, but as will.

So Schopenhauer says:

The thing-in-itself is Will—not rational, not moral, not even personal, but a blind, striving force that underlies everything.

Everything in nature—gravity, magnetism, animal instincts, human ambition—is this Will manifesting in various forms.


🔮 3. The World as Will and Representation

That’s the title of his big work:

  • “Representation” = the structured world of appearance, built by our mental forms (Kant-style).
  • “Will” = the inner reality, the driving essence behind all things.

So instead of Kant’s unknowable noumenon, Schopenhauer gives us a single metaphysical substance: Will, expressed through the world of appearance.


🎭 4. The Human Tragedy: The Will in Us

Now here’s where it gets dark:

  • The Will is irrational.
  • It never rests—it always strives, desires, wants.
  • This makes human life a constant cycle of want → satisfaction → boredom → want again.

So Schopenhauer says:

Existence is suffering because to exist is to be Will—and Will is never satisfied.


🧘 5. Escape Through Art and Renunciation

But he offers an escape:

  1. Aesthetic Experience:
    • When we contemplate beauty (especially music), we briefly step outside the Will’s grasp.
    • Music, in particular, is a “direct expression of the Will” and can show us the structure of inner reality.
  2. Asceticism / Denial of the Will:
    • Think monks, saints, mystics.
    • By turning away from desire, we can quiet the Will and glimpse inner peace.

He ends up oddly close to Buddhism: the world is suffering, and the only freedom is renouncing desire.


🏁 TL;DR

  • Kant said: we can’t know the thing-in-itself.
  • Schopenhauer said: actually, we can, because we are it—the Will is the inner essence of all things.
  • Life is driven by blind striving, and we suffer because we are that striving.
  • Our only hope is brief transcendence through art, or deeper liberation through denying the Will.

Want to see how this shaped Nietzsche? He read Schopenhauer as a teen and called The World as Will and Representation “a thunderbolt.”